Thursday, March 12, 2015

Statutory and Constitutional Interpretation

Scalia discusses two distinct types of interpretation in his initial essay, statutory and constitutional. Statutory interpretation, for Scalia at least, only looks at the text itself to offer a reasonable interpretation. He identifies two major problems with a non-textualist method, namely one that uses legislative intent. The first problem is that, because of judges cherry-picking elements of the record and the modern functioning of Congress, it “is much more likely to produce a false or contrived legislative intent than a genuine one.” (32). The second is the inherent challenge it provides to democratic government and the separation of powers, particularly how it constrains the power of the legislature to the benefit of judges (18). Personally, I find this to be an engaging case at the statutory level because of how it engages interpretation at both the theoretical and practical level.

When Scalia moves to constitutional interpretation, he attempts to apply his textualist method to the Constitution. Due to the nature of the Constitution, though, he can really only give a theoretical justification for his views. Even with its immense practical consequences, constitutional interpretation is more about what an abstract idea like freedom of expression entails, rather than a clear-cut ban on forced quartering of soldiers. This seems to create problems for Scalia’s argument, especially when he discusses something like the tyranny of the majority. He’s particularly concerned that, under an evolutionary interpretation, the Bill of Rights “will be committed to the very body it was meant to protect against: the majority.” (47). Despite his concern for politicized judges, that doesn’t seem to matter much if everyone agreed with Scalia. Everyone, using the same original meaning, would, instead of being influenced by modern majorities, be beholden to the original majority’s view. As a result, Scalia seems to have not completely solved problems he has on the theoretical side, much less the practical side.  

On a side note, does anyone know Scalia’s thoughts on the Lochner-era Court, which invalidated regulatory schemes on what is essentially economic freedom grounds? I would love to know how he reconciles this with his view of the “rock-solid, unchanging” Constitution of several decades ago.

1 comment:

  1. I think you're right Tim, and I think Dworkin agrees with you. Dworkin writes on the difference between "semantic" originalism and "expectation" originalism, rightly classifying Scalia as the former. A "semantic" originalist, he writes, is one who, "insists the rights-granting clauses be read to say what those who made them intended them to say" (119). A semantic reading, then, "dates" the reading to an understanding of the justices' position. As you write, "Everyone, using the same original meaning, would...be beholden to the original majority's view." Dworkin, I think, would agree that a semantic reading simply perpetuates former interpretations, which could easily have majoritarian roots. Scalia's interpretations may be better than an evolutionary ones for other reasons, but protection against majority rule (or justices as legislators) is not one of them.

    ReplyDelete